Immanuel Kant is a revolutionary and polemic figure in the history
of Western philosophy. His idealism has commonly been seen as a reaction to Enlightenment
assumptions that knowledge can only be grounded in human reason and science.
Kant, without dismissing either discipline, attempted to place philosophy in dialogue
with science, as he was very much moved by people like Rousseau and Hume:
praising the former for his emphasis on the senses and the latter for his
unprecedented skepticism. By attempting to synthesize our experiences of the
world to the demands of reason, Kant believed he was doing for philosophy what Copernicus
had done for astronomy.
It may be helpful to give a brief layout of Kant’s philosophy
which he lays out in The Critique of Pure
Reason in order to better understand his ideas about the sublime in Critique of Judgment. Kant’s beginning
premise is that all human knowledge can be based on experience. Whatever data
our five senses reports to us about reality is what we can know. But Kant was a
skeptic, after the fashion of Hume who had argued that it is simply irrational
to presume that our experience of reality corresponds to reality itself. In
other words, if my senses report to me that I am seeing a waterfall, that doesn’t
mean that in reality, I can know what a waterfall is. All I can know is my experience of the waterfall, as I perceive
it through my senses. My experience of such objects is what Kant refers to as the
phenomenon. However, besides my experiences
of things there are the noumenon—the
things as they exist in themselves, which we can know nothing about. In short,
the reality we apprehend is not reality in itself. It is merely our experience or
“take” on reality (Western Philosophy Russell).
Now, in Critique of
Judgement, we can see similar methods of these two categories of knowledge
operating at the level of understanding sublimity and beauty. What Kant says
about the sublime, in terms of the mathematically sublime, is that its location
does not reside in the external world (noumenon),
but rather “only in our own ideas” (LABL 45). Speaking of sublimity in nature,
Kant is consistent by saying it “does not reside in any of the things in
nature, but only in our own mind” (LABL 46). These feelings provoked in us by
the sublime, and registered by our senses, are our experiences (phenomenon) of such things, and not of
reality. Since Kant was attempting cohesiveness between our reason and our
imagination (the former demanding a limit to what we can know, while the latter
entertains limitlessness), our mind can apprehend a “reflective judgment” about
the object, but not the object itself (noumenon),
regarding the sublime. As Kant says, this feeling (experience) of the sublime, arises
from our “inadequacy of [our] imagination in the aesthetic estimation of
magnitude to attain to its estimation by reason” (LABL 45). Our imagination and
reason collide and produces a state of mind in which we place a value judgment on
the object that is to be called sublime; but our state of mind is what warrants
to be called sublime, not the object, since the object is part of the reality,
which our reason can never fully grasp. Our minds can receive the data
collected from reality through our senses, but we can only formulate concepts
(such as sublimity) according to that data, and this helps us understand our
experiences. But, according to Kant, things in themselves are unknowable.
Some critics have argued that Kant therefore denies the
existence of reality, since that is the world containing the noumenon which are unknowable. But other
critics believe that is not the case: the noumenon
exists because it gives rise to the phenomenon
which we experience. Perhaps it’s best to think that Kant contends there are
two realities: the reality we experience and the reality itself. Because of
Kant’s education in Leibnez philosophy and because of his attempt towards a conciliate
epistemology between science and philosophy, I like to think the latter is
true. Either way, Kant is a figure that continues to be controversial and influential
for his profound genius.
My favorite way to explain noumenon is a pencil in a glass of water. The pencil looks bent due to the water's ability to refract light but in actuality, the pencil is straight. Therefore what you see is not necessarily how things are.
ReplyDeleteI think Wordsworth hints at how noumenon and phenomenon interact when he describes a "dark invisible workmanship that reconciles// discordant elements, and makes them move//in one society." lns 353-356
I like that. And of course, even some hard-boiled empiricists such as Locke or Berkeley would agree that our senses can be deceiving.
ReplyDeleteThat's a good line from Wordsworth. Thanks for bringing it up.