From "Nihilism" to "Justice"
The selection from Zizek's In Defense of Lost Causes is
fascinating, insightful, frustrating, and surprising. Above all, I found it intellectually exciting. However, I want to explore the main
outlines of his argument because I believe it has some problems, avoiding his
interesting digresssions, like those on science, Christianity, and free will. One of the main arguments that
underlies his discussion is that "there are no background coordinates of
our world" -- that is, there is no "Big Other" (God, Nature, or
any creative, ordering principle) (445).
Reality is "a meaningless chaotic manifold" (444). Nietzsche said much the same about
reality, denying God and order, but ended up positing a kind of "Big
Other" -- the will to power.
Zizek makes a similar move, denying one thing, on the one hand, and
positing something else, rather obliquely, on the other. The end of absolute nihilism can only
be suicide or selfish hedonism. As
Yvor Winters said to Robinson Jeffers, if he really believed it was better to
be a rock than a human being, he should kill himself. Zizek turns out not to be an absolute nihilist.
Throughout
the selection, Zizek returns to various forms of "an anonymous Fate beyond
social control" (459). These
include the process of capitalism, the development of science and technology,
the destructive natural processes set in motion by human beings. As Marx and Engels observed of
capitalism, "All that is solid melts into thin air, all that is holy is
profaned." Science and
technology (with genetic engineering, cloning, and nanotechnology) has shown
that there is no natural order, no human nature, no Nature at all. The study of evolution demonstrates that there is no
evolution as a progressive development.
Rather, species have evolved because of "catastrophes" and
"broken equilibria" (442) Any equilibrium is secondary;
disequilibrium is primary.
The
concern to prevent the runaway destructive natural processes from destroying
the earth and the human race -- ecology -- Zizek identifies as "the
predominant form of ideology of global capitalism" (439). Although ecology purports to attempt to
change humans' relationship to the earth, it is actually resistant to change
and has "the anti-totalitarian post-political distrust of large collective
acts" (440). Thus, ecology is
a false alternative which does not fundamentally challenge capitalist
hegemony. While dwelling on
catastrophe, it hopes deep down that it will not really happen, and in this it is
reinforced by our common sense, which is habituated to everyday reality and
does not believe this reality can be disrupted (445).
Zizek,
at moments, challenges these anonymous, seemingly uncontrollable
processes. He resists the absolute
authority of science. He discusses
"the way science functions as ... an ideological institution" which
provides certainty and stamps out or marginalizes "heretics"
(446). He expresses discomfort
with tinkering with the human genome or attempting to create a synthetic
cell. Instead of deeming 90
percent of the human genome "junk DNA," he wonders if this
"junk" is important and we just don't understand how life works -- how "an 'infinite'
(self-regulating) organic structure arises" (441). He also balks at seeing the human being
as completely empty and without agency, as a "blind circuit of
neurons" (446).
Given
such challenges, we might expect Zizek to offer some replacement "Big
Other" or at least some principle for action. And he does this in a rather sly way. Zizek argues that the various forms of
the "Big Other" stop us from acting in the face of possible
destruction. The Big Other as a
"'reified' social system" or a natural process cannot be stopped
because it has become an unconquerable reality -- an In-itself (453). This reification of abstract processes comes
about through prosopopoeia.
Through personification, the processes -- whether capitalist
development, scientific progress, or natural processes -- become objective
realities. However, he makes sure
to defend Hegel's "objective Spirit." This Spirit is objective and real, independent of
individuals, but it is not related to a "collective or spiritual super-Subject"(454). There is no collective Subject beyond
individual human beings. But the
objective spirit is related to individuals in so far as it is the
"presupposition of their activity" (454).
His
sly move occurs rather abruptly at the end of the chapter as a rationale for
action. The ecological challenge should be met by reinventing and reviving what
Zizek ironically calls the "'eternal Idea' of revolutionary-egalitarian
Justice" and later "egalitarian terror" (460, 461). Since there is no Big Other for Zizek,
but rather a "meaningless chaotic manifold," he is not positing this
Justice as an In-itself, a reality. But, we can suppose, we should act as if this Justice existed, fully conscious that it is an invention. Furthermore, if we act as "a
people" with "large-scale collective decisions," are we not also
reinventing the "collective or spiritual super-Subject"? (461, 454).
Will this subject act with reference to a Hegelian "objective
spirit"? And most important
for the implementation of his proposals, if the collective Subject and Justice
are inventions, who will define them
and, therefore, make the collective decisions? The "terror" is presumably necessary, according to
Zizek, in order to avert catastrophe and save human lives. In the process of administering justice
through terror, some people will have to receive "ruthless
punishment" and perhaps die in order for the majority to be saved. Is Zizek, then, promoting a kind of
totalitarian utilitarianism?
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.